Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus (English): Difference between revisions

no edit summary
No edit summary
No edit summary
Line 1,415: Line 1,415:


(If I fix my eyes first on the corners ''a'' and only glance at ''b'', ''a'' appears in front and ''b'' behind, and vice versa.)
(If I fix my eyes first on the corners ''a'' and only glance at ''b'', ''a'' appears in front and ''b'' behind, and vice versa.)
5.55 We must now answer a priori the question as to all possible forms of the elementary propositions.
The elementary proposition consists of names. Since we cannot give the number of names with different meanings, we cannot give the composition of the elementary proposition.
5.551 Our fundamental principle is that every question which can be decided at all by logic can be decided off-hand.
(And if we get into a situation where we need to answer such a problem by looking at the world, this shows that we are on a fundamentally wrong track.)
5.552 The "experience" which we need to understand logic is not that such and such is the case, but that something ''is''; but that is ''no'' experience.
Logic ''precedes'' every experience — that something is ''so''.
It is before the How, not before the What.
5.5521 And if this were not the case, how could we apply logic? We could say: if there were a logic, even if there were no world, how then could there be a logic, since there is a world ?
5.553 Russell said that there were simple relations between different numbers of things (individuals). But between what numbers? And how should this be decided — by experience ?
(There is no pre-eminent number.)
5.554 The enumeration of any special forms would be entirely arbitrary.
5.5541 How could we decide a priori whether, for example, I can get into a situation in which I need to symbolize with a sign of a 27-termed relation ?
5.5542 May we then ask this at all? Can we set out a sign form and not know whether anything can correspond to it?
Has the question sense: what must there ''be'' in order that anything can be the case?
5.555 It is clear that we have a concept of the elementary proposition apart from its special logical form.
Where, however, we can build symbols according to a system, there this system is the logically important thing and not the single symbols.
And how would it be possible that I should have to deal with forms in logic which I can invent: but I must have to deal with that which makes it possible for me to invent them.
5.556 There cannot be a hierarchy of the forms of the elementary propositions. Only that which we ourselves construct can we foresee.
5.5561 Empirical reality is limited by the totality of objects. The boundary appears again in the totality of elementary propositions. The hierarchies are and must be independent of reality.
5.5562 If we know on purely logical grounds, that there must be elementary propositions, then this must be known by everyone who understands propositions in their unanalysed form.
5.5563 All propositions of our colloquial language are actually, just as they are, logically completely in order. That simple thing which we ought to give here is not a model of the truth but the complete truth itself.
(Our problems are not abstract but perhaps the most concrete that there are.)
5.557 The ''application'' of logic decides what elementary propositions there are.
What lies in its application logic cannot anticipate.
It is clear that logic may not conflict with its application.
But logic must have contact with its application.
Therefore logic and its application may not overlap one another.
5.5571 If I cannot give elementary propositions a priori then it must lead to obvious nonsense to try to give them.
5.6 ''The limits of my language'' mean the limits of my world.
5.61 Logic fills the world: the limits of the world are also its limits.
We cannot therefore say in logic: This and this there is in the world, that there is not.
For that would apparently presuppose that we exclude certain possibilities, and this cannot be the case since otherwise logic must get outside the limits of the world: that is, if it could consider these limits from the other side also. What we cannot think, that we cannot think: we cannot therefore ''say'' what we cannot think.
5.62 This remark provides a key to the question, to what extent solipsism is a truth.
In fact what solipsism ''means'', is quite correct, only it cannot be ''said'', but it shows itself.
That the world is ''my'' world, shows itself in the fact that the limits of the language (''the'' language which I understand) mean the limits of ''my'' world.
5.621 The world and life are one.
5.63 I am my world. (The microcosm.)
5.631 The thinking, presenting subject; there is no such thing.
If I wrote a book "The world as I found it", I should also have therein to report on my body and say which members obey my will and which do not, etc. This then would be a method of isolating the subject or rather of showing that in an important sense there is no subject: that is to say, of it alone in this book mention could ''not'' be made.
5.632 The subject does not belong to the world but it is a limit of the world.
5.633 ''Where in'' the world is a metaphysical subject to be noted?
You say that this case is altogether like that of the eye and the field of sight. But you do ''not'' really see the eye.
And from nothing ''in the field of sight'' can it be concluded that it is seen from an eye.
5.6331 For the field of sight has not a form like this:
[[File:TLP 5.6331en.png|250px|center|link=]]
5.634 This is connected with the fact that no part of our experience is also a priori.
Everything we see could also be otherwise.
Everything we can describe at all could also be otherwise.
There is no order of things a priori.
5.64 Here we see that solipsism strictly carried out coincides with pure realism. The I in solipsism shrinks to an extensionless point and there remains the reality co-ordinated with it.
5.641 There is therefore really a sense in which in philosophy we can talk of a non-psychological I.
The I occurs in philosophy through the fact that the "world is my world".
The philosophical I is not the man, not the human body or the human soul of which psychology treats, but the metaphysical subject, the limit—not a part of the world.